To the know-it-alls: Baloney

To the know-it-alls: Baloney

Photo by Joshua Sortino on Unsplash

Originally published 2 August 1993

In 1933, to cel­e­brate its own cen­te­nary, the city of Chica­go host­ed a world’s fair cel­e­brat­ing a “Cen­tu­ry of Progress” in sci­ence and indus­try. The offi­cial guide book quot­ed the poet Whit­ti­er: “And step by step, since time began, I see the steady gain of Man.”

Since time began. And what about in the oth­er direc­tion? Will our knowl­edge of nature con­tin­ue to advance step by step till the end of time? Or are there lim­its to sci­en­tif­ic progress?

There is no such thing as unlim­it­ed progress in sci­ence, says Alan Cromer, a physics pro­fes­sor at North­east­ern Uni­ver­si­ty. He advances this view in an arti­cle in the May [1993] issue of the North­east­ern Uni­ver­si­ty Mag­a­zine, and in a book, Uncom­mon Sense: The Hereti­cal Nature of Sci­ence, to be pub­lished this fall by Oxford Uni­ver­si­ty Press.

Cromer writes: “Sci­ence requires the belief in an exter­nal world that is inde­pen­dent of our thought and wish­es, a world that oper­ates accord­ing to its own set of con­sis­tent rules. Once we know these rules — and today we know the essen­tial ones — we under­stand the basic mech­a­nisms that gov­ern the world.”

The laws of nature place lim­its on progress, says Cromer. Per­pet­u­al motion machines are impos­si­ble. Noth­ing can trav­el faster than the speed of light. Every­thing is made of atoms. Prin­ci­ples such as these reside in the exter­nal world, not in our knowl­edge of the world.

From this, Cromer draws con­clu­sions that many will con­sid­er pes­simistic: Trav­el to the stars is impos­si­ble and com­mu­ni­ca­tion with extrater­res­tri­al civ­i­liza­tions is high­ly unlike­ly; the speed of land trav­el on Earth is approach­ing its upper lim­it; the moon land­ing may be an accom­plish­ment in space nev­er to be equaled; and so on.

We can expect break­throughs in those areas of knowl­edge where we are still large­ly igno­rant, says Cromer, such as mol­e­c­u­lar biol­o­gy, brain research, and human behav­ior. But progress in those dis­ci­plines, too, is des­tined to come to an end. There is only so much to learn about nature, and when we know it, that’s it.

OK, so now we know where Cromer stands in the debate about progress that has raged at the heart of West­ern civ­i­liza­tion — firm­ly against what he calls “the notion of unbound­ed tech­ni­cal advancement.”

The oth­er side of the debate is defined by what the his­to­ri­an J. B. Bury called “the illu­sion of finality.”

Cromer is trapped in the illu­sion of finality.

In fact, many physi­cists these days seem prone to the illu­sion of final­i­ty. They talk about The­o­ries of Every­thing, about know­ing the mind of God, about final the­o­ries. We have nature pret­ty much doped out, they say; all that’s left are mop­ping up exer­cis­es. Once we know nature’s laws, tech­no­log­i­cal progress will come to a halt.

Baloney.

There is a mis­take and a dan­ger in the illu­sion of finality.

The mis­take is to assume that our for­mu­la­tion of nature’s laws is the same as the laws them­selves. Cromer is right when he says that sci­ence requires a belief in an exter­nal world that is inde­pen­dent of our thought. But our knowl­edge of the world is pro­vi­sion­al, metaphor­i­cal, incom­plete. It is sheer hubris to assume that human thought ful­ly cap­tures nature’s essence.

For one thing, our minds are mere frag­ments of a uni­verse that is vast, per­haps infi­nite, beyond our know­ing. Can the part encom­pass the whole? Cromer would per­haps say that although the uni­verse is vast, the laws of nature are few in num­ber and eas­i­ly con­tained with­in the human brain. But that view too con­fus­es human sci­ence with the real­i­ty that inspires it.

I would guess that in the year 2093 the physics of the year 1993 will seem as par­tial and ten­ta­tive as the physics of Aris­to­tle seems to us today. Progress dur­ing the next cen­tu­ry will occur in two ways. First, we will learn more about fun­da­men­tal things, such as the way the par­ti­cles of mat­ter are relat­ed to pure space-time. Sec­ond, com­put­er sci­ence will pro­vide pow­er­ful new metaphors and math­e­mat­i­cal meth­ods for phys­i­cal explanation.

The dan­ger with the illu­sion of final­i­ty is that we will sur­ren­der opti­mism, vision, and wide-eyed antic­i­pa­tion to the New Age char­la­tans who pur­vey an open-end­ed cos­mic des­tiny to any­one who for­goes rea­son for blind faith.

The illu­sion of final­i­ty also con­tributes to the chron­ic bore­dom that afflicts our time and makes us easy prey to those who would turn us into con­sumerist automatons.

Between the “notion of unbound­ed tech­ni­cal advance­ment” and the “illu­sion of final­i­ty” we should choose the for­mer, not because we can prove the pos­si­bil­i­ty of what has not yet come to be, but as a mat­ter of opti­mism and hope.

Con­tin­ued devel­op­ment of sci­ence and tech­nol­o­gy will pose huge moral and social dilem­mas for future gen­er­a­tions, entrain­ing dire prob­lems as well as hope­ful solu­tions. Con­fi­dence in the idea of progress will help us avoid pes­simism and defeat.

Share this Musing: